Armstrong's Universals In Armstrong's 'Universals as Attributes', he argues for a different way of considering universals. He in part considers what kinds of universals there are: are there disjunctive universals, or perhaps negative universals, and are conjunctive universals somehow different from these? Armstrong lays out relatively straightforward arguments for why disjunctive and negative properties aren't universals. He considers only property universals, and assumes the Principle of Instantiation (that every universal must be instantiated, either past, present, or future) (200). A disjunctive property universal is a disjunction of properties, say C (or) M. Suppose there are two objects, each having one of the disjuncts but lacking the other. Then each has the universal C (or) M. Armstrong says that "surely that does not show that, in any serious sense, they thereby have something identical" (201). The point of a universal was to talk about a thing that would be the same at all times it instantiated that property. Therefore, it shouldn't be the case that a disjunctive property is a universal. Further, there also seems to be a link between universals and causal powers. A thing having a particular charge C (if C is a universal), grants that thing particular causal powers. Say that it does not have mass M. Then it has the disjunctive property of C (or) M. If this were a universal, should it not likewise affect the object's causal powers? But this doesn't seem to be the case: we haven't added anything to the object that would seem to change its powers. The suggestion therefore is that C (or) M is not a genuine universal, whilst C is. Armstrong thinks similarly for negative universals. If an object having C is the instantiation of a universal, then not having C is not instantiating a universal. Then is (not) C a universal? If we were to examine all of the objects which lack a particular charge, is there anything common to them all? While there may be a coextensive property that happens to align with not having charge C, it doesn't seem that this is a factor in the objects themselves; namely that they lack C. A causal argument can also apply. It seems funny to say that absences of universals are universals because it doesn't appear to be the case that absences have causal powers. However, for cases of the conjunction of universals, it _is_ the case that having both C (and) M is a universal: every object that instantiates C (and) M instantiates both C and M, and from the perspective of causality it will certainly have causal powers because of this. It might even be the case that instantiating this universal provides greater causal powers than having either C or M alone! It seems that the strongest objection to Armstrong's view is his dismissal of negative universals. While we are happy for instance to say that 'a lack of water caused his death', but unhappy to say something like 'a lack of poison causes us to remain alive', Armstrong says that in both of these instances, "if the surface understanding of the first statement is correct, then the second statement should be understood in the same way and thought to be true" (201). Armstrong points out that, as these are causal truths, a counterfactual account of them tells us "very little about the actual causal factors" (201) in each case. But simply because these causal accounts aren't terribly insightful doesn't make them any less true, they're simply less adequate accounts of the causal relation that purportedly exists. The lack of poison is just one of the causes of my being alive, along with properly functioning organs and an environment conducive to sustaining life. These factors may all change: certainly the introduction of poison to my system would have a notable kind of cause, and so it isn't necessarily the case that there not being any poison should be an uninteresting one. At the very least, an exploration of the change in situation from 'a lack of poison' to 'there being poison' is an interesting one, and so we shouldn't dismiss absences as causes outright, simply because they aren't terribly informative out of a context. Armstrong might find a suitable reply in several different avenues. One of the trickier ones may be insisting that causal stories be informative ones, that tell us about the factors involved in a situation to help us understand what the relation is. This seems difficult, if not missing the point, being that a causal story isn't necessarily a story about _the_ cause, but rather _a_ cause of an event. I think Armstrong would rather appeal to the notion of bare particulars. Armstrong says that a bare particular exists "outside states of affairs would not be clothed in any properties or relations" (205). Particulars instantiate universals, which is what gives them their "nature, kind, or sort" (206). Thus, a particular of this kind wouldn't have any such nature or kind. There isn't anything much to make of these kinds of particulars. An instance of this sort of thing would be a void (at least on a certain understanding of the void). So in cases such as the void being said to have causal powers, these statements would only _seem_ to be instances of causal relations. In the actual world, however, no such relation can attain, because there are no states of affairs in the world that seem to bear this kind of relation. Now, in the cases similar to the examples Armstrong gives at the beginning of the paper ('a lack of poison', for instance), this might be harder to describe - this is one property that is attribute to a particular - but it nevertheless could probably be properly fleshed out in the way that Armstrong wants it to be. ________________________________________________________________________________ Dilyn Corner (C) 2020-2022